Summary: The universe may very well be infinite, and hence contain an infinite amount of happiness and sadness. This causes several problems for altruists; for example: we can plausibly only affect a finite subset of the universe, and an infinite quantity of happiness is unchanged by the addition or subtraction of a finite amount of happiness. This would imply that all forms of altruism are equally ineffective.
Like everything in life, the canonical reference in philosophy about this problem was written by Nick Bostrom. However, I found that an area of economics known as "sustainable development" has actually made much further progress on this subject than the philosophy world. In this post I go over some of what I consider to be the most interesting results.
NB: This assumes a lot of mathematical literacy and familiarity with the subject matter, and hence isn't targeted to a general audience. Most people will probably prefer to read my other posts:
- Ridiculous math things which ethics shouldn't depend on but does, which includes such interesting tidbits as: why standard calculus teaches children to be immoral and why the Banach-Tarski paradox implies we should means test Medicare and
- Kill the young people, whose name speaks for itself
1. Summary of the most interesting results
- There’s no ethical system which incorporates all the things we might want.
- Even if we have pretty minimal requirements, satisfactory ethical systems might exist but we can’t prove their existence, much less actually construct them
- Discounted utilitarianism, whereby we value people less just because they are further away in time, is actually a pretty reasonable thing despite philosophers considering it ridiculous.
- (I consider this to be the first reasonable argument for locavorism I've ever heard)
2. Definitions
In general, we consider a population to consist of an infinite utility vector (u0,u1,…) where ui is the aggregate utility of the generation alive at time i. Utility is a bounded real number (the fact that economists assume utility to be bounded confused me for a long time!). Our goal is to find a preference ordering over the set of all utility vectors which is in some sense “reasonable”. While philosophers have understood for a long time that finding such an ordering is difficult, I will present several theorems which show that it is in fact impossible.
Due to a lack of latex support I’m going to give English-language definitions and results instead of math-ey ones; interested people should look at the papers themselves anyway.
3. Impossibility Results
3.0 Specific defs
- Strong Pareto: if you can make a generation better off, and none worse off, you should.
- Weak Pareto: if you can make every generation better off, you should.
- Intergenerational equity: utility vectors are unchanged in value by any permutation of their components.
- There is an important distinction here between allowing a finite number of elements to be permuted and an infinite number; I will refer to the former as “finite intergenerational equity” and the latter as just “intergenerational equity”
- Ethical relation: one which obeys both weak Pareto and finite intergenerational equity
- Social welfare function: an order-preserving function from the set of populations (utility vectors) to the real numbers
3.1 Diamond-Basu-Mitra Impossibility Result1
- There is no social welfare function which obeys Strong Pareto and finite intergenerational equity. This means that any sort of utilitarianism won’t work, unless we look outside the real numbers.
3.2 Zame's impossibility result2
- If an ordering obeys finite intergenerational equity over [0,1]N, then almost always we can’t tell which of two populations is better
- (i.e. the set of populations {X,Y: neither X<Y nor X>Y} has outer measure one)
- The existence of an ethical preference relation on [0,1]N is independent of ZF plus the axiom of choice
4. Possibility Results
We’ve just shown that it’s impossible to construct or even prove the existence of any useful ethical system. But not all hope is lost!
The important idea here is that of a “subrelation”: < is a subrelation to <’ if x<y implies x<’y.
Our arguments will work like this:
Suppose we could extend utilitarianism to the infinite case. (We don't, of course, know that we can extend utilitarianism to the infinite case. But suppose we could.) Then A, B and C must follow.
Technically: suppose utilitarianism is a subrelation of <. Then < must have properties A, B and C.
Everything in this section comes from (3). This is a great review of the literature.
4.1 Definition
- Utilitarianism: we extend the standard total utilitarianism ordering to infinite populations in the following way: suppose there is some time T after which every generation in X is at least as well off as every generation in Y, and that the total utility in X before T is at least as good as the total utility in Y before T. Then X is at least as good as Y.
- Note that this is not a complete ordering! In fact, as per Zame’s result above, the set of populations it can meaningfully speak about has measure zero.
- Partial translation scale invariance: suppose after some time T, X and Y become the same. Then we can add any arbitrary utility vector A to both X and Y without changing the ordering. (I.e. X > Y ó X+A > Y+A)
4.2 Theorem
- Utilitarianism is a subrelation of > if and only if > satisfies strong Pareto, finite intergenerational equity and partial translation scale invariance.
- This means that if we want to extend utilitarianism to the infinite case, we can’t use a social welfare function, as per the above Basu-Mitra result
4.3 Definition
- Overtaking utilitarianism: suppose there is some point T after which the total utility of the first N generations in X is always greater than the total utility of the first N generations in Y (given N > T). Then X is better than Y.
- Note that utilitarianism is a subrelation of overtaking utilitarianism
- Weak limiting preference: suppose that for any time T, X truncated at time T is better than Y truncated at time T. Then X is better than Y.
4.4 Theorem
- Overtaking utilitarianism is a subrelation of < if and only if < satisfies strong Pareto, finite intergenerational equity, partial translation scale invariance, and weak limiting preference
4.5 Definition
- Discounted utilitarianism: the utility of a population is the sum of its components, discounted by how far away in time they are
- Separability:
- Separable present: if you can improve the first T generations without affecting the rest, you should
- Separable future: if you can improve everything after the first T generations without affecting the rest, you should
- Stationarity: preferences are time invariant
- Weak sensitivity: for any utility vector, we can modify its first generation somehow to make it better or worse
4.6 Theorem
- The only continuous, monotonic relation which obeys weak sensitivity, stationary, and separability is discounted utilitarianism
4.7 Definition
- Dictatorship of the present: there’s some time T after which changing the utility of generations doesn’t matter
4.8 Theorem
- Discounted utilitarianism results in a dictatorship of the present. (Remember that each generation’s utility is assumed to be bounded!)
4.9 Definition
- Sustainable preference: a continuous ordering which doesn’t have a dictatorship of the present but follows strong Pareto and separability.
4.10 Theorem
- The only ordering which is sustainable is to take discounted utilitarianism and add an “asymptotic” part which ensures that infinitely long changes in utility matter. (Of course, finite changes in utility still won't matter.)
5. Conclusion
I hope I've convinced you that there's a "there" there: infinite ethics is something that people can make progress on, and it seems that most of the progress is being made in the field of sustainable development.
Fun fact: the author of the last theorem (the one which defined "sustainable") was one of the lead economists on the Kyoto protocol. Who says infinite ethics is impractical?
6. References
- Basu, Kaushik, and Tapan Mitra. "Aggregating infinite utility streams with intergenerational equity: the impossibility of being Paretian." Econometrica 71.5 (2003): 1557-1563. http://folk.uio.no/gasheim/zB%26M2003.pdf
- Zame, William R. "Can intergenerational equity be operationalized?." (2007). https://tspace.library.utoronto.ca/bitstream/1807/9745/1/1204.pdf
- Asheim, Geir B. "Intergenerational equity." Annu. Rev. Econ. 2.1 (2010): 197-222.http://folk.uio.no/gasheim/A-ARE10.pdf
"The universe may very well be infinite, and hence contain an infinite amount of happiness and sadness. This causes several problems for altruists; for example: we can plausibly only affect a finite subset of the universe, and an infinite quantity of happiness is unchanged by the addition or subtraction of a finite amount of happiness. This would imply that all forms of altruism are equally ineffective."
I have no particular objection to those, unlike me, interested in aggregative ethical dilemmas, but I think it at least preferable that effective altruism - a movement aspiring to ecumenical reach independent of any particular ethical presuppositions - not automatically presume some cognate of utilitarianism. The repeated posts on this forum about decidedly abstract issues of utilitarianism with little or no connection with the practice of charitable giving is, perhaps, not particularly helpful in this regard. Most basically however, I object to your equivalence of altruism and utilitarianism as a matter of form: that should not be assumed, but qualified.
The problems with extending standard total utilitarianism to the infinite case are the easiest to understand, which is why I put that in the summary, but I don't think most of the article was about that.
For example, the fact that you can't have intergenerational equity (Thm 3.2.1) seems pretty important no matter what your philosophical bent.